The Subject
Ghiath el-Marzouk
The subject is divided [or split],
only insofar as (s)he speaks.
Lacan
Preliminary
This article puts forward the antithesis between the two
psychical counterparts of the ego (the objective counterpart of
its conscious representation and the subjective counterpart of
its unconscious representation), so as to probe their ensuing
implications in psychoanalysis, a discipline which is ultimately
concerned with one specific person. The article will, thus,
argue that the subjective counterpart of the ego is synonymous
with that person as a generalization or an abstraction,
collectively referred to in the Lacanian formulation as ‘the
subject’. It will touch on the two oppositional ‘behavioural’
imports of the term (the active import and the passive one) and
its unresolved theoretical status in Freud’s writings, a status
which may have been the fundamental reason for the term to
occupy a central position in Lacan’s writings. From both
philosophical and linguistic viewpoints, an attempt will be made
to explain the three distinctive types of the subject in terms
of the logical problem that Lacan posits as a new sophism,
namely, the impersonal subject, the undefined (or anonymous)
subject, and the personal subject. Special emphasis will be
placed on the personal subject (as well as the ‘personal’ ego
that is concealed within it), thereby signifying the two-fold
analogy between the objective-subjective counterparts of the ego
and the conscious-unconscious representations of the subject
(being the ‘person uttering I’), respectively. Reference
will also be made to the conceptual difference between
Jakobson’s and Lacan’s definitions of the personal pronominal
I as a ‘shifter’: while Jakobson considers the category an
‘indexical symbol’, Lacan regards it as an ‘indexical
signifier’, in which case the diametrical opposition between the
subject’s statement and his/her enunciation is underlined. This
diametrical opposition will be characterized as a prerequisite
for the subject’s inherent hesitation, and therefore his/her
immanent division, between the conscious I (in the
statement) and the unconscious I (in the enunciation), a
notion of the divided (or rather split) subject which appears to
originate from Freud’s concept of the ‘split ego’ (or
Ich-Spaltung ‘split-I’ in his terms). Finally, the article
will show that the subject is inherently hesitant and immanently
divided because of his/her predestined alienation and
estrangement through language’s constant representation of
his/her existence and thinking in the same manner, the language
which creates the world of things, at the one end, and whose
main medium of transmission is the signifier in the world of
ideas, at the other end.
Exposition
As discussed in a preceding article published
within this series, the human psyche seems to be
constantly torn in the face of the enduring antagonism between
the reality principle (the guider of the ego) and the pleasure
principle (the controller of the id), an antagonism which may
well be aggravated by the severity and austerity of the morality
principle (the governor of the super-ego), as a lurking
socially-designated principle (cf. el-Marzouk, 2008a;
2008b). This enduring antagonism is indubitably
entrenched in the general predilection of the psychical
apparatus for the obdurate adherence to pleasurable libidinal
sources (be they ‘sexual’ in the literal sense or, otherwise, in
the figurative senses of predications) on the one hand, and
entrenched in its extreme arduousness with the abjuration of
these sources on the other hand. If the morality principle is
ethically debilitated in its effect, and subsequently becomes
incapable of censoring the pleasure principle, then the ethical
debilitation would be transferred, as it were, onto the reality
principle which would, in turn, be confronting either (or both)
of two possible alternatives: firstly, the complete forfeiture
of its capacity to maintain the conative and wishfully
orientated equilibrium that is indispensable for the ego’s
self-gratification; and secondly, the absolute submission of its
rationality, which appears to be ethically debilitated by
transference also, to the irrational vagaries of the id’s
sexualization (or libidinization). With the perceivable
repercussions of these two possible alternatives, the human
psyche would be far more stringently torn between the ego being
driven into the chaotic realm of the id (in which case the
former entity would be as unorganized as the latter entity) and
the ego being self-indulgent in the uncontrolled satisfaction of
the conative trends that are secreted by the id (in which case
the former entity would be as passionate as the latter entity).
In either case, there does not appear to exist an escape route
for the ego’s salvation, since the entity, as “a [rider] on
horseback, in its relation to the id”, would be either doomed to
social oblivion (the first alternative) or condemned to social
ostracism (the second alternative). Yet, even in the case of the
ego’s deliverance from both alternatives, where the morality
principle is not ethically debilitated, the human psyche would
still be torn between the inescapable polarity between the false
judgements that are consciously formulated by the ego and the
true judgements that are unconsciously formulated by the id,
with the extrinsic falseness referring to the objective
counterpart of the conscious ego and the intrinsic trueness
alluding to the subjective counterpart of the unconscious ego.
It now becomes evident that, upon the least manifestation of
this polarity between false judgements and true judgements, the
human psyche would comprise three interdependent entities (the
passionate id, the rational ego, and the censoring super-ego).
In addition, the rational ego would, in turn, also exhibit its
objective counterpart in the conscious representation and its
subjective counterpart in the unconscious representation, the
representation that is apposite to the crucial similitude
between the connate id and the connate-acquired ego in the
ensuing presence of the acquired super-ego. If the subjective
counterpart of the unconscious ego is synonymous with the sense
of identity mentioned in a previous article (cf. el-Marzouk,
2007a; 2007b), and if the bulk of psychoanalysis,
be it theoretical or practical, is fundamentally concerned with
one specific person, then the subjective counterpart of the
unconscious ego is synonymous with that person as a
generalization or an abstraction, collectively referred to as
‘the subject’, whose typical particularization or reification is
exemplified by the infant or the patient.[1]
It is worthy of mention, in this respect, that Freud himself
does not use the term ‘the subject’ as a theoretical construct
in its own right, but asserts rather that the human psyche, in
its tripartite entirety, is still governed by three further
distinctive antitheses, viz. subject-object, pleasure-unpleasure,
and active-passive. By the antithesis subject-object he simply
means the multitudinous interaction between the ego and the
non-ego, thereby signifying a conceptual parallelism between the
ego and the subject at the one extreme, and a conceptual
parallelism between the non-ego and the outer world at the other
extreme. To him, this antithesis is “thrust upon the individual
organism at an early stage” and “remains, above all, sovereign
in our intellectual activity” at a later stage (Freud,
1915:131). Apart from the antithesis pleasure-unpleasure, which
determines human activities (human agency or will) and is
associated with a determined scale of pent-up feelings, the
antithesis active-passive seeks to emphasize the duplex nature
of the subject in its ‘behavioural’ relationship with the object
(the outer world): primarily, the subject is passive (or
receptive) as long as it is stimulated by the outer world; and
secondarily, the subject is active (or productive) insofar as it
responds to the same world. It appears, therefore, that this
duplicate nature of the subject within a differential form of
antithesis (as well as its unresolved theoretical status in
Freud’s writings) may well have been the principal reason for
the construct as a whole to occupy a central position in Lacan’s
writings.
In this context, what can be readily extrapolated from Lacan’s
theorization on the construct of the subject as a generalization
or an abstraction is that it is, first and foremost,
characterized with a personal nature, contrary to the construct
which exhibits an impersonal nature and the construct which
displays an undefined (or anonymous) nature. With the pat
contention that “the subject is never more than supposed” in
connection with his/her disposition (cf. Lacan, 1975-6), these
three distinctive types of the subject, so it appears, are easy
to pinpoint but so difficult to explain, owing to the depth of
their philosophical and linguistic connotations alike, for which
reason an attempt will be made here to undertake this quite
complex task. In his extremely abstruse, yet brilliant and
stimulating, paper “Logical time and the assertion of
anticipated certainty: a new sophism”, Lacan puts forward a
logical problem as a new sophism, which may be summarized in the
following way: a warder summoned three choice prisoners and
declared to them that he was plenipotentiarily authorized to set
one of them free. But before the decision was to be made, the
warder entrusted the outcome to a logical test that the
prisoners agreed to undergo. The logical test dictated that an
unknown disk of five known identical disks, which differ only in
colour (three whites and two blacks), be fastened to each of the
prisoners between their shoulders (i.e. outside their direct
visual field). Proscribed were all indirect mediums of seeing
one’s own reflection and, of course, excluded were all sorts of
mutual communication, since the first of the three prisoners to
leave the cell and deduce the colour of his disk would avail
himself of the releasing measure. The warder, then, fastened
each of the three white disks to each of the three prisoners as
prescribed, and all three prisoners, upon contemplating one
another for a certain time, left simultaneously and deduced,
each individually, the perfect solution to the logical problem
(cf. Lacan, 1966b:161f.). Accordingly, Lacan restates the
solution in his words: “I am a white, and here is how I know it.
Since my companions were whites, I thought that, had I been a
black, each of them would have been able to infer the following:
‘If I too were a black, the other would have necessarily
realized straight away that he was a white and would have left
immediately; therefore I am not a black’. And both would have
left together, convinced they were whites. As they did nothing
of the kind [that is, as they hesitated], I must be a white like
them. At that, I made for the door to make my conclusion known”.
“All three thus exited simultaneously, armed with the same
reasons for concluding” (Lacan, 1966b:162).
Given the logical problem and its perfect solution, there appear
to exist two suspended motions with no spatial order, which
enable the three prisoners (henceforth, the subjects A, B, and
C) to evince their deduction, even though the crucial functions
of these motions are elemental to logical ambiguity. The first
suspended motion is marked by the reasoning that subject A
imputes to either subject B or subject C (had subject A been a
black): had subject B been a black too, subject C would have
seen two blacks (subject A and subject B), and would have
realized that he was a white without hesitation (and vice
versa with respect to subject C). It is, therefore, either
subject B’s hesitation which enables subject C to realize that
he was a white or subject C’s hesitation which enables subject B
to realize that he was a white too, thereby constituting what
may called, ‘disjunctive hesitation’ as a marker of the first
suspended motion. The second suspended motion, on the other
hand, is marked by the reasoning that subject A imputes to both
subject B and subject C (had subject A been a black): had both
subject B and subject C realized that they were whites on the
basis of the first suspended motion (which is marked by the
afore-said disjunctive hesitation), they would have left
simultaneously without hesitation. It is, therefore, the
realization of both subject B and subject C that subject A was
in fact a white which made both subject B and subject C hesitate
over whether to decide that they were whites, a differentiated
form of hesitation which establishes instead what may be called,
‘conjunctive hesitation’ as a marker of the second suspended
motion. Since all three subjects, upon contemplating one another
for a certain time, did realize that they were whites, and did
subsequently leave with certainty simultaneously, each subject
had been enabled by the two suspended motions to deduce the
perfect solution to the logical problem. Thus, the two suspended
motions appear to have functioned as what may be called,
‘aporetic signifiers’ (or ‘blind spots’ in the optical sense),
simply because the subjects’ synchronous deductions were not
founded on what they did actually see (the three white disks),
but rather on what they did not see (the two black disks). In
consequence, of the three logically possible combinations (●●○,
●○○, ○○○), the two combinations (●●○, ●○○), which existed only
as aporetic signifiers (or blind spots) as such, did nonetheless
enable each of the three subjects to correctly deduce the one
and only one combination (○○○) as a pregiven.[2]
Given the two suspended motions and their functions as aporetic
signifiers, there seem to exist three evidential moments
with no temporal order,
moments
which enable the subject (be it A, B, or C) to evince his/her
deduction, since the logical values of these moments prove to be
of a differentiated form and increasing order. The first
evidential moment is marked by the reasoning which is based on
the first combination (●●○) as
a certifiable conditional statement (If one sees two blacks,
one knows that one is a white.), thereby signifying a
logical exclusion as a result
(i.e. the combination
(●●●) is excluded). The first
evidential moment, therefore, represents itself as the glancing
moment, since the protasis of the certifiable conditional
statement (viz. the antecedent if one sees two blacks)
as a pregiven is converted into its apodosis (viz. the
consequent one knows that one is a white) as a given.
Hence, the subject that adopts the apodosis of the
certifiable conditional statement alludes to the impersonal
subject in the form of the partitive impersonalization (one
knows that...). The second evidential moment is marked by
the reasoning that is founded on the second combination
(●○○) as an uncertifiable conditional
statement instead (If one were a black, the two whites one
sees would surely know that they are whites (without
hesitation).), thereby signifying an intuitive knowledge of
something that exists beyond the factual givens (i.e. the sight
of the two whites within the combination (○○)).The
second evidential moment, therefore, manifests itself as the
comprehending moment (which includes the glancing
moment), since each of the two whites would see a black and a
white within the combination (●○),
and would thus know that he/she is a white upon his/her
semblable’s hesitation. Hence, the subject whose performance is
suspended by mutual causality upon adopting the apodosis
of the uncertifiable conditional statement refers to the
undefined (or anonymous) subject in the form of the
interdependent undefinedness (or anonymity) (one knows upon
the other’s knowledge that...). The third evidential moment
is marked by the reasoning that is constructed on the third
combination (○○○) as a
volitional nonconditional statement this time (One wants to
declare oneself a white before the other two whites want to
declare themselves whites.), thereby signifying, in this
case, a judgemental assertion about oneself exhibiting
logical originality due to the persistence of the (previous)
comprehending moment in reflection. The third evidential
moment, therefore, characterizes itself as the concluding
moment (which culminates in the subject’s true
deduction), since each of the three whites depends on the
observed and/or perceived hesitation
of the other two semblables. Hence, the subject that adopts the
entire volitional statement points to the personal
subject in the form of the individual personalization (I know
that...).
With respect to the impersonal subject, who is now
discernible from the afore-mentioned apodosis of the certifiable
conditional statement in the form of the partitive
impersonalization (one knows that...), the construct is
accounted for in terms of what is known as the ‘noetic
subject’ or the ‘cogitative subject’ (Lacan,
1966b:170). As the term ‘noetic’ (or ‘cogitative’) would
indicate, the construct appears to draw the attention to the
paramount significance of the mental processes that are
consciously utilized in perception and in cogitation, especially
when these mental processes operate in isolation from other
mental processes which are similar to them, but nonetheless
function outside their sphere. By analogy, the impersonal
subject would connote the psychical independence of the human
agency under consideration from any other human agency, with the
latter human agency being simply designated ‘the other’ (who, in
turn, establishes his/her own psychical independence). Given the
partitive impersonalization (one knows that...), the
intended impersonalization of the subject means, therefore, that
the human agency under consideration is known to itself, but it
is not known to the other (self) at the first evidential
moment (the glancing moment). From this angle, the most
approximate structural representation that may convey the noetic
(or cogitative) signification of the construct of the impersonal
subject is perhaps what is called in linguistics, the
‘impersonal passive’ structure, as in the following very
communicable utterance in any tangible mode of language, be it
the phonemic mode in speaking or the graphemic mode in writing:
It is stated that Lacan may or may not be a
synthesis of Freud and de Saussure. Thus, the only possible
person (or, rather, the impersonal subject) who might actually
have made this statement would lurk somewhere in the ‘darkness’
of the purely grammatical subject of the sentence It, a
nominal expletive that can, without affecting the absence of
self-knowledge of the person in question, be substituted for the
partitive quantifier Someone as the immediate
maker of the statement (e.g. Someone stated
that Lacan may or may not be a synthesis of Freud and de
Saussure.). Here, the impersonal subject has an impersonal
ego that is neither active nor passive in the sense intended by
Freud, since there does not exist any other ego to establish
with it the psychical counterpart of stimulus-response
interaction, given the third antithesis ‘active-passive’ which
‘behaviourally’ represents this interaction.
With regard to the undefined (or anonymous) subject, who is now
understandable from the afore-mentioned apodosis of the
uncertifiable conditional statement in the form of the
interdependent undefinedness (or anonymity) (one knows upon
the other’s knowledge that...), the construct is explained
in terms of the purely reciprocal subject who introduces the
being of ‘the other as such’ (Lacan, 1966b:170).
Accordingly, the undefined (or anonymous) subject would only
recognize himself/herself in the other, and would subsequently
discover his/her psychical independence (or rather his/her sense
of identity) only in absolute equivalence with the other. This
indicates that the human agency under consideration, in virtue
of its pure reciprocity, is entirely commensurate with, and
equally replaceable by, any other human agency. Hence, the
undefined (or anonymous) subject does not seem to deviate from
the impersonal subject at bottom, since both constructs are
looked upon as potentially transitional, so to speak (or as
potentially ‘transitive’, in Lacan’s terminology
in
the original French, a terminology
which may have something to do with the lexical meaning of
identification in its ditransitive implementation referred to in
a previous article; namely, the relationship of equation or
identicalness (cf. el-Marzouk, 2007a; 2007b)).
Thus, in the light of the interdependent undefinedness (or
anonymity) (one knows upon the other’s knowledge that...),
the undefinedness (or anonymity) of the subject would denote
that the human agency under consideration is known to itself,
too, but in a manner which is contingent upon the self-knowledge
of the other at the second evidential moment, the comprehending
moment (and, of course, vice versa in respect of this
otherness, given its pure reciprocity as well). Again, the most
approximate structural representation that may disclose the
purely reciprocal signification of the construct of the
undefined (or anonymous) subject is what is perhaps called in
linguistics, the ‘impersonal active’ structure (in
contradistinction with the ‘impersonal passive’ structure in the
case of the impersonal subject). This approximation can be
observed in the use of certain quantifiers, such as, the
distributive quantifier Everyone or the universal
quantifier All, as the immediate makers of the statement
(e.g. Everyone stated that Lacan may or may not
be a synthesis of Freud and de Saussure; All stated that
Lacan may or may not be a synthesis of Freud and de Saussure.).
Similarly, the undefined (or anonymous) subject has an undefined
(or anonymous) ego that is neither passive nor active in the
sense intended by Freud as well, since all other detached egos
would establish with this ego all the psychical counterparts of
stimulus-response interaction, given also the third antithesis
‘active-passive’ which ‘behaviourally’ reflects this interaction.
Concerning the personal subject, on the contrary, the subject who
is now perceivable from the afore-said entire volitional
nonconditional statement in the form of the individual
personalization (I know that...), the construct is
characterized with the logically original subject, the
dually knowing subject who assumes
both the impersonal subject and the undefined (or anonymous)
subject at each of the first two evidential moments: the
glancing moment and the comprehending moment (Lacan, 1966b:170).
It follows that the personal
subject, at either (or both) of these two evidential
moments specifically, would both establish his/her
psychical independence from the other (as is the case with the
impersonal subject) and manifest his/her absolute
proportionateness with, and thence
his/her equivalent substitutability for, the other (as is the
case with the undefined (or anonymous) subject). Form this
standpoint, therefore, the confluence of the psychical
independence and the absolute proportionateness in question
would appear to touch on the inceptive evidence of the personal
subject’s immanent division (or rather fissure), as will be seen
presently. However, the personal subject is radically
differentiated from both the impersonal subject and the
undefined (or anonymous) subject at the third evidential moment,
the concluding moment, since neither of the latter two subjects
is able to assume any of the personal subject’s qualities at any
evidential moment, owing to his/her nontransitionalness (or
nontransitivity, on the analogy of Lacan’s original
term ‘transitive’). This would indicate that the afore-mentioned
judgemental assertion can only be formulated by the personal
subject about himself/herself at the concluding moment, and is
thus definitively unimputable to him/her by any other (subject),
whether reservedly or unreservedly. It is the impossibility of
the imputation itself which is imputable to the personal
subject due to his/her perceived idiosyncrasy and his/her
perceivable uniqueness, qualities or attributes that are
achieved by the human agency under consideration as
unintentional activities of self-affirmation (or even
self-determination). Accordingly,
in the light of the individual personalization (I know
that...), the personalization of the subject would
certainly imply that the human
agency under consideration may or may not be known to itself,
whether it is unknown to the other (at the glancing moment) or
known to itself in a manner that is contingent upon the
self-knowledge of the other (at the comprehending moment). For
this reason, the seemingly approximate structural representation
which may well allude to these
unintentional activities of self-affirmation (or
self-determination) would be a signifier with a highly
specific property, a signifier that ought to unconsciously
negate the enunciation of the human agency under
consideration upon the employment of any of
the personal pronominals I, You, etc., where each
pronominal is the immediate maker of the statement (e.g. I
stated that Lacan may or may not be a synthesis of Freud and de
Saussure.). Here, the personal subject, as opposed to either
of the two other subjects, has a personal ego that is both
passive and active in Freud’s sense, since not all other
(though detached) egos would establish with it the psychical
counterparts of stimulus-response interaction, given the third
antithesis ‘active-passive’ which ‘behaviourally’ represents
this interaction, as well.
It also follows that the signifier
which ought to unconsciously negate the subject’s
enunciation figures nowhere in the exemplified statement, since
the personal pronominal I suggests what Jakobson
calls the ‘shifter’, a term which he borrowed from Jespersen
(1923) to draw the attention to the ‘person uttering I’,
thereby stressing the dual function of the shifter as an index
and a symbol within the class of indexical symbols (Jakobson,
1957:132). Notwithstanding, of course, the subtle, yet
apparently significant, distinction between the two terms in
semiotics: while the index points to Peirce’s idea of the sign
which establishes a contiguous relationship with its referent
(e.g. smoke is an index of fire), the symbol refers to de
Saussure’s notion of the sign which constitutes a more
discontiguous relationship with its referent instead (e.g. a red
blotch is a symbol of several diseases) (cf. Peirce, 1932).
Here, Lacan seems to have aptly reversed the concept of the
index by contrasting it with the signifier (and not with
the symbol per se), so as to underline, in turn, the
opposition between the function of the symptom in medicine as an
index of a physical disease (or diseases) and the function of
the symptom in psychoanalysis as a signifier of a given
psychopathology, the afore-mentioned symptomatic signifier (cf.
Lacan, 1966a:129; 1966b:348) (see, also, note
2). For this reason, Lacan characterizes the shifter with what he
calls, the ‘indexical signifier’ (rather than the indexical
symbol in Jakobson’s sense) to highlight a further distinction
between the subject’s enunciation (as being a set of indices)
and his/her statement (as being a set of signifiers, in
contrast), thereby indicating the inherent hesitation (or
doubtfulness) of the subject in representing the ‘person
uttering I’. Lacan cites the
famous example (I am
lying) to clarify the further
distinction as such,
where the subject’s enunciation enunciates implicitly the
intention of lying and deceiving and
his/her statement states explicitly the actual utterance
as a
whole, meaning that the index
of the enunciation is absent, while the signifier of the
statement is present (Lacan, 1964:138f.). The only
structural representation that may ‘index’ the index of
enunciation in French is the negative particle ne ‘but
not’, as in his oft-cited example (avant qu’il ne soit
avéré qu’ils n’y comprennent rien), from which the removal
of the particle ne causes the enunciation to lose its
pejorative force (Lacan, 1966a:298; 1966b:677).
This particle ne is comparable with the English adverbial
but in certain examples (e.g. I cannot but
think that...), as correctly pointed out by Fink (1995:39),
though the adverbial itself can
never be semantically superfluous as he erroneously understands
it, since its removal causes the enunciation to lose its
compulsive force, too. As a result, the real personal
subject would lurk somewhere in the ‘darkness’ of ne in
French or but in English if it figures in the previous
exemplified statement (e.g. I cannot but
state that Lacan may or may not be a synthesis of Freud and de
Saussure.). This very
statement would now imply the polarization between the conscious
I behind the signifier (the personal pronominal
I itself) in the statement itself, on the one hand,
and the unconscious I behind the index (the
compulsive adverbial but) in the enunciation, on the
other hand.
It is this sense of the personal subject (as well as the personal
ego that is contained within it) on which Lacan places special
emphasis, viz. the subject who is discernible from the
unconscious I behind the index as a generalization
or an abstraction.[3]
Thus, the further distinction between the subject’s enunciation
and his/her statement just mentioned would not only indicate the
inherent hesitation (or doubtfulness) of the subject (the
‘person uttering I’), but would also signify his/her
immanent division (or fissure) referred to earlier, with the
latter signification dichotomizing the subject into the
conscious I behind the signifier and the unconscious I
behind the index. In fact, the subject’s immanent
division (or fissure), as such, has already been hinted at in
suggesting the two psychical counterparts of the ego, given the
antithesis between false judgements (on the part of the ego) and
true judgements (on the part of the id), as mentioned at the
outset. While the objective counterpart of the ego in its
conscious representation corresponds with the conscious I
behind the signifier, the subjective counterpart of the ego in
its unconscious representation coincides with the unconscious
I behind the index, with the subjective counterpart
being germane to the crucial similitude between the connate id
and the connate-acquired ego in the arising presence of the
acquired super-ego. Furthermore, this distinction between the
conscious I and the unconscious I would also
reflect the distinction between the Cartesian subject, who is
by definition conscious of his/her existence at the moment of
cogitation (I think, therefore I exist),
and the logical inverse of the same
Cartesian subject, “who appears at the
moment when doubt is recognized as certainty” (Lacan, 1964:126),
thereby connoting the intended disjunction between cogitation
and existence instead (Either I (do not) think, or
I (do not) exist). It seems, therefore, that Lacan’s
very notion of the divided (or fissured) subject is initially
derived from Freud’s conception of the ‘split ego’ (or
Ich-Spaltung ‘split-I’) in the sense of being a deformed
outcome of disavowal, a conception which may explain the
aetiologies of certain psychopathological cases. At first,
this conception of the split
ego is rather tersely spoken of in the case studies of neurosis
and psychosis, which would “reflect a failure in the functioning
of the ego” so long as this entity is consciously inclined to
“avoid a rupture [...] by effecting a cleavage or division of
itself” (Freud, 1923:217). Then, the same conception is later
argued at length but in the case study of fetishism (which is a
form of sexual perversion), whereby the ego of the fetishist is
split because one part of this ego seeks to deny the castration
complex (or its ensuing anxiety) –unlike the other part of the
ego that tends to accept the complex (or its ensuing anxiety)
as well (Freud, 1927:356; 1938a:463;
1938b:438f.). In other words, the ego of the fetishist
appears, in fact, to be an entity which is split between
masculine sexuality and feminine sexuality, respectively, given
the crucial difference between the two sexes in infantile sexual
behaviour, as explained in a previous article (cf. el-Marzouk,
2007a; 2007b).
From analogy, Lacan’s contention that the subject is divided or
split between enunciation and statement, the subject whom he
symbolizes as $ (barred S(ubject)), would clearly denote that
the extent of division or fissure is determined by the act of
speech: the subject is divided or split “only insofar as
he/[she] speaks”(Lacan, 1966a:269; 1966b:530).
This contention would amount to saying that it is “the subject
[who] designates his/[her] being by barring everything he/[she]
signifies” (Lacan, 1966a:288; 1966b:581). The same
contention would also indicate that the subject is seized by an
inherent form of hesitation (or doubtfulness), throwing him/her
from one part to another by all means, and that all of the
afore-said is a consequence of his/her predestined alienation
and estrangement through language’s constant representation of
his/her existence and his/her thinking alike. It is this
alienation and this estrangement which are inexorably connected
to the psychical transformation whereby the ego originally
identifies itself with an alter ego (Lacan, 1955-6:23).
Accordingly, the indexical signifier (or, simply,
the
signifier) would betray such inexorable attributes (division,
hesitation, and alienation) in the very
same way a parapraxis (a slip of the tongue, the ear, the pen,
etc.) would betray the
subject’s true intentionality, hence the injunction that the
subject operates as a construct of the unconscious (the
unconscious I) and not as a construct of the conscious
(the conscious I). Thus, Freud’s mention of the above
psychopathological cases (neurosis, psychosis, and perversion)
are considered by Lacan the three major clinical structures in
which neurosis, in particular, is the ‘normal’ clinical
structure due to the essential occurrence of the split within
the subject –unlike the ‘abnormal’ clinical structure of
psychosis where the same split does not seem to occur (Lacan,
1955-6:174; 1960-1:374f.). In consequence, the subject as a
generalization or an abstraction is,
basically, a neurotic subject as a by-product of language
with all its forms of association, a subject who is divided,
hesitant, and alienated at the very moment he/she expresses
his/her buried self through the medium of the signifier.
Summary
To summarize, the psyche is constantly torn between the polarity of
false judgements (on the part the conscious ego) and true
judgements (on the part of the unconscious id), a polarity which
may correspond with the two psychical counterparts of the ego
(the objective counterpart of its conscious representation and
the subjective counterpart of its unconscious representation),
given the crucial similitude between the ego and the id in a
given quantum of unconsciousness. If Psychoanalysis is
ultimately concerned with one specific person, then the
subjective counterpart of the ego would be synonymous with that
sense of person as a generalization or an abstraction,
collectively referred to as ‘the subject’. The term, in fact, is
not employed by Freud as a theoretical construct in its own
right, though it figures in his writings as an agency in
concomitance with the object to constitute one of the
three antitheses that govern the psyche in its entirety (viz.
subject-object, pleasure-unpleasure, and active-passive),
thereby stressing the dual nature of the subject in its
‘behavioural’ relationship with the object (passive and active).
This duplicate nature of the subject as a term (and its
unresolved theoretical status in Freud’s writings) may have been
the principal reason for the term to occupy a pivotal position
in Lacan’s writings, where three discrete types of the subject
are discernible with reference to the logical problem that is
posited as a new sophism. Firstly, the impersonal subject
who is explained in terms of the noetic (or cogitative) subject
in the sense that the intended human agency is psychically
independent of any other human agency, meaning that the
impersonal subject is known to himself/herself, but is not to
the other (e.g. It is stated that...;
Someone stated that..., etc.). Secondly, the undefined
(or anonymous) subject who is accounted for in terms the purely
reciprocal subject in the sense that the intended human agency
is absolutely proportionate with, and equally substitutable for,
any other human agency instead, meaning that the undefined (or
anonymous) subject is known to himself/herself in a manner that
is contingent upon the self-knowledge of the other (e.g.
Everyone stated that...; All
stated that…, etc.). Thirdly, the personal subject who is
characterized with the logically original subject, the
dually knowing subject who assumes the
first two types of the subject, but is radically differentiated
from them, owing to his/her idiosyncrasy and uniqueness,
attributes that are achieved by the intended human agency as
unintentional activities of self-assertion (or even
self-determination), thence denoting that the personal subject
may or may not be known to himself/herself, irrespective of the
other (viz. his/her self-knowledge) (e.g. I
stated that..., etc.). Whereas the affirmative mode of the
intended human agency in the statement is present (the conscious
I), its negative mode in the enunciation is absent (the
unconscious I), but may lurk behind the indexical
semlable of the adverbial but in certain utterances (e.g.
I cannot but state that..., etc.).
It is this notion of the subject as a construct of the
unconscious that has its considerable significance in the
Lacanian formulation, where the diametric opposition between
statement and enunciation reflects the subject’s inherent
hesitation and his/her immanent division, a notion of the
divided subject which derives from Freud’s concept of the split
ego, and which is taken as evidence of the
‘normal’ clinical structure of neurosis (unlike the
‘abnormal’ clinical structure of psychosis where the split does
not seem to occur). As a result, the construct of the personal
subject, who is basically a neurotic
subject in the ‘normal’ clinical structure, does indicate a
being who is hesitant and divided and alienated through
the language’s constant representation of his/her existence and
thinking alike, the language which creates the realm of things
and whose main medium of transmission is the signifier in the
realm of ideas.
*** *** ***
References
Fink, Bruce (1995): The Lacanian Subject: Between Language
and Jouissance. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Freud, Sigmund (1915): Instincts and Their Vicissitudes.
Penguin Freud Library, vol. 11.
Freud, Sigmund (1921): Group Psychology and the Analysis of
the Ego. Penguin Freud Library, vol. 12.
Freud, Sigmund (1923): Neurosis and Psychosis. Penguin
Freud Library, vol. 10.
Freud, Sigmund (1927): Fetishism. Penguin Freud Library, vol. 7.
Freud, Sigmund (1938a): Splitting of the Ego in the
Process of Defence. Penguin Freud Library, vol. 11.
Freud, Sigmund (1938b): An Outline of Psychoanalysis.
Penguin Freud Library, vol. 15.
Jakobson, Roman (1957): Shifters, verbal categories, and the
Russian verb. In his Selected Writings, vol. 2. The
Hague: Mouton (1971:130-147).
Jespersen, Otto (1923): Language: Its Nature, Development,
and Origin. New York.
Lacan,
Jacques (1955-6): The Seminar. Book III. The Psychoses. Trans.
Russell Grigg. Routledge (1993).
Lacan,
Jacques
(1960-1): Le Séminaire. Livre VIII.
Le Transfert.
Paris:
Seuil.
Lacan,
Jacques (1964): The Seminar. Book XI. The Four Fundamental Concepts of
Psychoanalysis. Trans. Alan Sheridan. Vintage (1998).
Lacan,
Jacques (1966a): Écrits: A Selection. Trans. Alan Sheridan.
Routledge (1997).
Lacan,
Jacques (1966b): Écrits. Trans. Bruce Fink.
Norton (2006).
Lacan,
Jacques
(1975-6): Le Séminaire. Liver XXIII. Le Sinthome. Est.
Jacques-Alain
Miller, Ornicar?, vol. 6.
el-Marzouk, Ghiath (2007a):
ÇáÏãÌ [Identification].
Damascus: Maaber.
el-Marzouk, Ghiath (2007b): Identification. Damascus:
Maaber.
el-Marzouk, Ghiath (2008a):ÇáÃäÇ
[The
ego]. Damascus: Maaber.
el-Marzouk, Ghiath (2008b): The ego. Damascus: Maaber.
Peirce, Charles S. (1932): Elements of Logic. In his
Collected Papers, vol. 2.
Cambridge: Hartshorne
& Paul Weiss.
[1]
Notice, here, that the subject
as a generalization or an abstraction points to the
universal implication of the term, strictly speaking,
and is therefore nothing to do with the definiteness of
the specific individual under consideration (i.e. the
infant or the patient in the non-generic sense). This
universal implication corresponds to Lacan’s notion of
generality, a notion which is diametrically
opposed to the notion of collectivity, especially
with reference to its logical conception. In his words:
“the collectivity is defined as a group formed by
the reciprocal relations of a definite number of
individuals –unlike the generality, which is
defined as a class abstractly including an indefinite
number of individuals” (Lacan, 1966b:174). Thus,
Lacan’s allusion to collective
psychology is reminiscent of Freud’s formulation of
group psychology, whose major focus is on
the constitution of the collective psychology of a group
on the basis of certain alterations in the individual
psychologies of its members –unlike Le Bon’s
formulation, where the emphasis is laid on “the
[psychical] alteration which the individual undergoes
when in a group” (Freud, 1921:99).
[2]
To refresh the memory as a
conceptual preamble to a forthcoming article on the
linguistic entity of the signifier, specifically, three
discrete types of the signifier have been mentioned thus
far, and may be re-adumbrated as follows. In a previous
article published within this series,
it is stated that, with the (intervening) inversion of
the Oedipus complex, the identifier assimilates one
single character-trait from the identified (as is the
case with young Dora who was imitating her father’s
tormenting catarrhal cough). This single character-trait
is considered to be a signifier, and is then introjected
under symbolic identification to
ultimately connote ‘identification with the symptom’.
The first mentioned type, therefore, is what may be
called, the ‘symptomatic signifier’ (the cough
itself). On the contrary, the infant’s most pristine
form of reflexive self-realization is also regarded as a
signifier, and is thus introjected instead under
imaginary identification to initially denote
‘identification with the imago’ in the mirror
stage. The second mentioned type, therefore, is what may
be called, the ‘specular signifier’ (the imago
itself) (cf. el-Marzouk, 2007a; 2007b)
–with the third newly
mentioned type in the text
being the ‘aporetic signifier’ (the suspended motion
itself). However, all such three types of the signifier
would operate outside the domain of language in
general
(whether the signifier is a
symptom or an imago or a suspended motion). For
this reason, the three types are classifiable under what
may be called, extra-linguistic signifiers,
in contradistinction
with what may be called, intra-linguistic signifiers,
the latter referring
in particular to those
signifiers which
would operate inside the
domain of language, as will be seen in a forthcoming
article.
[3]
Recall that the subject as a
generalization or an abstraction refers to the universal
implication of the term, where Lacan’s notion of
generality, unlike the
notion of
collectivity, “is defined as a class abstractly
including an indefinite number of individuals” (see note
1). The indefiniteness which defines generality
as such
is, therefore, attributed to the extendibility of the
logical problem discussed in the text by recurrence, a
mathematical process which underpins the application of
this problem to an infinite number of subjects, provided
that the number of the black disks is equal to the
number of the subjects minus one. Thus, if the warder
summons four choice prisoners (A, B, C, and D) and is in
possession of seven disks (four whites and three
blacks), then the solution to the problem may recur as
follows: A knows that he is a white. Since B, C, and D
were whites, A thinks that, were he a black, each of
them would infer the following: B knows that he is a
white. Since C and D were whites, B thinks that, were he
a black too, each of them would infer the following: ‘If
I too were a black, the other would know that he is a
white; therefore I am not a black’. As they all
hesitated, I must be a white like them. And so on and so
forth (cf. Lacan, 1966b:175, n.4).